Navigation Panel: Up | Forward | Graphical Version | PostScript version | SIMMER Home Page | Fields Institute Home | U of T Math Network Home

SIMMER

May 1997 Presentation Topic (continued)


A Sampling of Questions

Prime Numbers

Our concept of number has evolved over time from the natural numbers to the integers, and soon thereafter, to the rationals. From there the concepts of real and complex numbers were eventually developed.

Algebra over the integers is already an interesting subject. We call an integer p a prime number if its only divisors are +/- 1 and +/- p. (Exception: the numbers +/- 1 themselves are not called prime; they are called units instead).

Question 1: Can you show that there are infinitely many prime numbers?

There are many interesting questions about prime numbers. For instance, are there any primes with 100 digits? How many primes like this are there? These questions have become more important in recent years since constructing (and breaking!) many computer security systems depends on being able to factor huge numbers.

The Greeks

The rational numbers were a favourite of the Greeks, whose world view depended heavily on aesthetics and order. It was felt that any geometric quantity occurring could be represented by a rational number.

Question 2: Using a line segment (designated to be of length one), a straight edge and a compass, construct the diagonal of a square of side length one. That is, using these tools (all available to the Greeks!), construct a line segment that is the diagonal of a square of side length one. Can you show that this side length is not a rational multiple of the unit length? Phrased another way, can you show that sqrt(2) is not a rational number?

When this fact was discovered, it caused quite a sensation. Not only was a mathematical idea proven incorrect, but a whole philosophy was discredited.

Orderings

Let's turn our attention to the way that numbers are ordered. Of course, we all know how to count and this puts a natural ordering on the rational numbers: 1/2 <= 1 <= 2 <= 5/2. I hope to show you later that ordering numbers is actually a rather difficult and deep problem.

The positive integers have a nice property: there is a smallest positive integer (namely, 1). In fact, even if you throw away the number 1, or even if you throw away a whole collection of numbers (as long as you don't throw them all away!), there will still be among the remaining numbers one which is the smallest. This is called the well-ordering principle.

However, the rational numbers with their natural ordering do not satisfy the well-ordering principle.

Question 3: Show that there is no smallest positive rational number. This suggests that the Greek notion of an atom (a smallest indivisible amount) might not exist.

It is a surprising result from set theory that every set admits a well-ordering. Therefore, we can order the positive rational numbers in such a way that (a) for any two distinct numbers, one is larger than the other; and (b) in any collection of numbers (other than the empty set, of course), there's always a smallest number. However, this ordering is not at all the same as the usual ordering!

Question 4: Try to find an ordering on the positive rational numbers which has these properties.

Real Numbers

One might think that there is a natural ordering on the real numbers: compare them digit by digit. You'd be right, but there is a complication: the digit representation of a real number need not be unique.

Question 5: Show that 0.999... = 1. We say there are two ways to represent the number 1 in decimal notation. Are there any other ways to represent the number 1 in decimal notation?

This suggests that real numbers are much more complicated than ordinary old rational numbers. It is quite hard to get a hold of a real number: we need to know all of its digits. This really disturbed me when I was first learning mathematics. If this is the case, in what sense do we know that the number pi = 3.14... exists?

Monkeys

There are lots of interesting questions concerning the size of the integers. Of course, there are infinitely many integers but some odd things can happen.

Question 6: Two monkeys (Abe and Bonzo) come upon a clearing containing two barrels (A and B) and an infinite number of coconuts, conveniently labeled with the positive integers. Abe suggests two ways of filling the barrels. The monkeys can do this very fast, so that we can ask what will happen when ALL the coconuts are in the barrels. Which method should Bonzo agree to?

  1. [(A)] Abe puts 100 coconuts in barrel A (his barrel) and 1 in barrel B (Bonzo's barrel), 1000 coconuts in barrel A and 2 in barrel B, 10000 in barrel A and 3 in barrel B, et cetera.

  2. [(B)] Abe puts 100 coconuts in barrel B and removes the smallest numbered coconut in barrel B and puts it in barrel A, then puts 100 more coconuts in barrel B and removes the smallest coconut (there are now 199 coconuts in barrel B) from barrel B and puts it in barrel A. He continues in this way.

Intuitively it seems obvious that there are more real numbers than rational numbers and more rational numbers than integers. What do you think about the relative sizes of such infinite collections of numbers? In what sense do we mean that there are more reals than integers? These are interesting questions to ponder.

Candyman's Dilemma

Question 7: John checks his pocket and finds he has less money than the cost of a comic book ($1.05). Instead, he decides to buy candy at the corner store. There are three types of candy: Appletarts (A) at 3 cents each, Butterscotch Kisses (B) at 5 cents each, and Cinamonos (C) at 7 cents each. John says, if I buy only Appletarts then I will have 2 cents left over, if I buy only Butterscotch Kisses then I will have 4 cents left over and if I buy only Cinamonos then I will have 5 cents left. How much money does John have in his pocket?

We'll discuss this, and other similar problems, in terms of formulas known to ancient Chinese mathematicians. We'll also explain how modern mathematics studies these problems using modular arithmetic.

In the integers modulo 7, there are only seven numbers: 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, and 6. You can divide 3 by 2 in this number system: the quotient is 5, since 2 times 5 equals 3 in arithmetic modulo 7.

Question 8: Try to show that you can always divide any number by any non-zero number, in the integers modulo 7. Can this still be done in the integers modulo 12?

Question 9: In the integers modulo 7, compute 2^7, 3^7 and 5^7 (there is a clever way to do this last one). What do you notice? Can you prove your conjecture?



Navigation Panel: 

  Go up to Introduction and Contents
  Go forward to Solutions
  Switch to graphical version (better pictures & formulas)
  Access printed version in PostScript format (requires PostScript printer)
  Go to SIMMER Home Page
  Go to The Fields Institute Home Page
  Go to University of Toronto Mathematics Network Home Page